III Practical Evaluation: Why "Non-constitutional Pluralism"?
Contexts clearly make a difference, as I’ve tried to show in the last section. Still we need some general criteria to evaluate institutional settings and policies. We would, rightly, not be satisfied with generalized statements like ‘it all depends’. In this section I try to develop some general moral, ethical and realist arguments23 in favor of "non-constitutional pluralism" in order to criticize the unquestioned predominance of the utopia of strict separation. For two reasons my evaluation remains rough and sketchy. First, the practical evaluation is complex and very much underresearched and, second, limits of space forbid a detailed discussion of all relevant issues. I decided to give an overview of the many problems and dilemmas involved and, consequently, had to bracket many important debates and to sidestep deeper discussions of other problems I touched upon. I have chosen to bracket many of the general questions in the controversy on cultural and religious pluralism on which political philosophers have mainly, sometimes even exclusively focused. Why should we accept cultural pluralism as a fact instead of fighting it? Why should we even strife to promote it? If we want to promote cultural pluralism which normative arguments are more convincing: perfectionist ethical arguments (the good life) or moral arguments (justice as fairness)? Can they be combined and, if so, how? If cultural pluralism is a good thing in itself, should the state promote it or should that be left to civil society or to ‘private’ actors? Is there a crucial distinction between cultural pluralism and religious pluralism? etc. The main reason for bracketing these issues is that they have been much more on the spot24 than the relations between cultural and institutional pluralism and, particularly, the more ‘down to earth’ and muddy issues of varieties of institutional settings and of policies. Bracketing these questions, however, does not mean that I would be agnostic about them. Living in culturally and religiously diversified societies, for me, is not a regrettable fact. It is enjoyable and a good thing. Broadly speaking there are two types of normative arguments in favor of cultural pluralism: perfectionist arguments of a good life (intrinsic value of diversity) and moral arguments that "justice as fairness" or "evenhandedness" requires recognition of diversity. Even if one recognizes that moral arguments cannot be completely neutral regarding values of a good life, I favor moral arguments based on historical and structural inequalities because all stronger and more meaningful notions of perfectionism sit uncomfortably with the fact of deep cultural and religious pluralism and deep disagreement on most matters of a good life. Fairness arguments, to me, are more minimalist and convincing. They combine two broad ideas. First, the fact that the state has historically not been ‘neutral’ but has actively promoted and guaranteed deep inequalities between majority and minority religions and is still doing so, morally requires at least some redress. Second, meaningful notions of substantive and informed freedom of choice are critical not only regarding state-enforced religious assimilation but also regarding societally enforced assimilation. If these combined minimalist moral arguments in favor of religious pluralism would be convincing, perfectionist pleas would only strengthen my case for institutional pluralism. If not, we would be forced back into the ongoing general discussion.
III.1 Moral Evaluation
Religious Freedoms
The fact of moral pluralism impinges on the moral evaluation of the four institutional options. The debate on the two religion clauses of the First Amendment has shown (Bader 1999) that moral principles are indeterminate. This does not imply, however, that “anything goes”. Each interpretation and each institutional arrangement has to be compatible with the moral and constitutional principle of religious freedom.
‘(1) Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion; this right includes freedom to change his religion of belief and freedom, either alone or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief, in worship, teaching, practice and observance. (2) Freedom to manifest one’s religion or beliefs shall be subject only to such limitations as are prescribed by law and are necessary in a democratic society in the interests of public safety, for the protection of public order, health or morals, or for the protection of the rights and freedoms of others’ (ICPR Art 9).
This human right of religious freedom is conventionally understood to guarantee two different freedoms: The freedom to belief, or the freedom of individual conscience and the freedom to practice religion in worship, ritual, teaching, observance (whether, as usual, collectively or individually, whether in “private” or in “public” spaces). And the freedom of (organized) religion (sects, denominations, churches) from illegitimate state control.25 Any productive interpretation of religious freedoms has to recognize serious inherent tensions.
The negative freedom from illegitimate state control seems to mandate not only “no aid” to religions but more generally “no involvement”.26 As all other negative freedoms, however, the freedom of individual believers and of individual and collective religious practices from persecution and suppression requires at least some state-involvement for two reasons. First, it is not only directed against state-interference, but also against persecution, oppression and all other forms of illegitimate interference by other (organized) religions (majority religions amongst them) as well as by other “secular” groups and organizations (see Shue 1995:13). The state has the obligation to protect all (organized) religions from such interference. Second, religious freedom protects not only individual freedom of consciousness and religious practice but also collective practice of organized religions (‘equal respect for religions taken as collective wholes’ (Parekh, PSI 18; see HLR Note 1987:1740-81)) and collective autonomy easily contradicts individual religious freedoms.
In my view, a liberal-democratic state has the duty to protect individual believers against their “own” religious group, their organizations and leaders. Freedom of religious belief and practices, like all other freedoms, is constrained by the equal religious liberties of other believers and by all other civil, political and social rights which are equally part of the constitutions of modern, social, liberal-democratic states.27 Many examples come to mind where religious beliefs and individual or collective practices - guaranteed by “free exercise” - are incompatible with other human rights. Religiously legitimized practices of caste, bondage, slavery are surely incompatible with the most minimalist interpretation of modern freedom and equality. In her ‘Religion and Women’s Rights’ Martha Nussbaum provides a quite extensive list of problem areas and cases in which women’s individual human rights apparently conflict with freedom of traditional religious practices as interpreted by religious organizations and leaders.28 Practices of sati (immolation of widows following their husband’s death), of domestic violence, stranger-rape, marital rape, sexual abuse and genital mutilation obviously conflict with minimalist interpretations of a universal right to life and bodily integrity. Religiously legitimated practices of discrimination of women in employment, in marriage- and divorce law29 are at least very dubious. Why can we not avoid this ‘apparent dilemma for the modern liberal regime’30 by insisting on a rigorously individualistic, secularist interpretation of human rights, by fiercely attacking all “group rights”, including any collective autonomy for (organized) religions, by prescribing all separate codes or systems of religious laws and insisting on a ‘uniform civil code’ as most standard-liberals do?31 Unfortunately, this “solution” neglects the problem that actual freedoms of religious practices do not fall from heaven and need collective arrangements, at least under conditions of serious inequality. Group rights and some form of “collective autonomy” are needed by religious minorities to achieve more freedom from ‘intrusive interference’ both from actual states and from organized majority religion(s). Only under “ideal circumstances” would they become less important.32 But how to achieve a more sensible balance between protection of vulnerable individuals and groups inside religious minorities against minority organizations and leaders, and outside protection of vulnerable religious minorities against religious majorities and ‘their’ state?33 An extensive secularist and individualist interpretation of human rights would not leave much of the hallowed religious freedoms, on one hand. An extensive particularist interpretation of collective religious autonomy (so strongly preferred by traditionalist religious leaders) would lead, on the other hand, to a limitless toleration of the intolerant and intolerable, to a complete neglect of the rights of non-believers, other religions, women, children. Obviously, no easy answers can be expected, no easy solutions are available.
The positive freedom to belief and practice, emphasized by an accommodationist reading of the “Free Exercise Clause” (McConnel, see HLR Note 1987:1642) seems to ask for a more substantive involvement by the state than the minimally required involvement to guarantee the negative freedoms. It is often interpreted to require at least some "assistance or aid” to religions, some materially “equal treatment of religions”.34 Libertarians and other radically individualist liberals deny any such duty. For them, equal treatment is reduced to equality before and in the law and the absolute priority of liberty discounts any more substantive notion of equality of religions.35 “Aid” to religions is none of the state’s business. Only in this way, a strictly and consequently equal treatment of all religions (majority or minority) and of nonbelievers can be achieved. This position is also consequent in its neglect of structural social inequalities in general, of religions in particular. All moderate liberal democrats, social liberals, social democrats and liberal-democratic socialists criticize these individualistic radicals. Guided by more substantive notions of equality, they have to balance liberties from and liberties to, have to take inequalities into account, and have to find ways and means of “involvement” compatible with relational neutrality.
“Strong” establishment is clearly incompatible with religious freedom. The fact that the principle of religious freedom is invoked neither by proponents nor by opponents of complete dis-establishment during the PSI-debate indicates that it is ‘beyond dispute in any liberal society’ (Parekh, PSI 19). Existing “weak” establishment in England is understood to be fully compatible with the principle which demarcates the minimal moral requirement any variety of “establishment” has to satisfy in order to be morally or legally defensible at all. “Constitutional pluralism” is more explicit in the guarantee of religious freedoms to a plurality of organized religions. “Non-constitutional pluralism” and “Non-Establishment + private pluralism” most clearly express this fundamental principle. Contrary to predominant American opinion, however, “non-constitutional pluralism” may be a stronger option for two reasons. First, it is obvious that actual freedoms of belief, practice and organization do not fall from heaven and that constitutional or legal protection alone can never serve as their only guarantees. Their guarantee should therefore not be left to “law” and Supreme Courts alone. Public and political pressures by organized religions helps to remind “benevolent” religious majorities (including judges) of discriminatory practices.36 Formal recognition of organized religions is an important political and legal asset. Secondly, with regard to the freedom of (organized) religions from (illegitimate) state control, the three typical situations, distinguished above, differ. On the one hand, it is actually much more difficult to minimally control individualized religious beliefs and practices and loosely organized “invisible” sects (think of many recent examples of (enforced) collective “millenarist” suicide) compared with more organized sects (think of Bhagwan or Scientologists) and organized churches.37 Legal or constitutional recognition of churches by states with liberal democratic constitutions requires at least verbal recognition of religious freedoms of others, religious pluralism, obedience to (sensitive interpretations of) the law of the country and also some minimal actual commitment to liberal-democratic principles. Actual institutionalization and formal recognition heighten the possibilities and the means of state control. Organized religions, and particularly their elites and leaders (may) tend to become dependent upon tax exemptions, subsidies and other material, legal, political, symbolic privileges. This opens ways and means of exerting effective influence by government and local administration on churches, on one hand, and by leaders, representatives, spokespeople of churches themselves on laity on the other hand. Both forms of influence may be illegitimate: the first one may illegitimately restrict religious freedoms far beyond the minimal control required by principles of liberal-democratic constitutions; the second one seriously strengthens the power-resources of traditionalist leaders, elites and bureaucrats inside religious organizations and thereby weakens the chances of lay believers to liberalize and democratize their “churches” if they wish so. It is one of the paradoxes of institutionalization that growing influence on the external world has to be paid with the price of growing influence from outside and from above.38 State control may go beyond the tolerable long before the threshold of “Erastian establishment” has been passed, and this is the reason why religious organizations may resist any “formal” institutionalization. Then, however, they have to pay the price of losing important resources to exert influence on the external world. This dilemma is well-known from the historical struggle of all emancipation movements, be it workers, blacks, women, gays and lesbians or religious minorities. Again, no easy solutions are available.
Democracy and Political Citizenship
Political citizenship has to be equal for all citizens irrespective of their “race”, sex, gender, ethnicity, class or religion. Democratic principles like political liberty and equality and the corresponding political rights preclude all particularist categorization of specific groups, all specific groups rights and all forms of institutionalized political pluralism, so it is often said. All options to institutionalize religious pluralism seem thus incompatible with liberal democracy. Difference-blind legal rights, however, are not enough to achieve higher degrees of actual political neutrality of the state, of political society and civil society, neither in matters of sex and gender, of ‘race’ and ethnicity’ nor in matters of religion (Bader 1999).39
“Strong establishment” is not only incompatible with religious freedoms, it also implies de jure and/or de facto exclusion (or discrimination) of persons adhering to other (organized) religions or infidels from the right to vote, to stand for candidate and to equal access to public service, from the freedoms of political communication and association, and so forth. Religious second class citizenship is obviously morally wrong and incompatible with liberal-democratic constitutions. Like all morally permissible forms of modern, democratic political pluralism (e.g. “associative democracy”), all options to institutionalize religious pluralism have to live up to these minimal moral requirements. Granted effective political rights and freedoms, however, do the requirements of equal political citizenship require “complete dis-establishment”? Do they favor “non-establishment” compared with “weak” and “plural establishment”, as the Supreme Court consistently has ruled? Do they make a relevant difference between the two options of non-establishment?
Anne Phillips seems to think that only “dis-establishment” or “non-establishment” are defensible options. She distinguishes three alternative ways of thinking about the question of what democratic equality means in the context of a multicultural and -religious society (PSI, 24ff). The first view is a strongly assimilationist one (either in a civic republican version or in an ethnic nationalist version). The second view is more ‘accommodating to different practices and values, so long as these remain within a broadly private sphere in which people can get on with their own chosen affairs, and a public realm ordered around a rather minimalist set of shared presumptions’ (25). This classical liberal solution to cultural and religious difference falls ‘far short of genuine recognition or mutual acceptance’ for lack of public recognition. Her own third view requires ‘that differences should be more explicitly acknowledged and brought onto the political stage’ (26).40 However, she claims that such public deliberation and democratic decision-making itself requires complete dis-establishment, a fully secular state and political society.
“Weak establishment” of one church fares badly for two reasons: it does not officially recognize the plurality of (organized) religions in civil society, political society and in the state, and it tends to curtail the actual political opportunities of minority religions. “Constitutional pluralism” and “non-constitutional pluralism” correct both deficiencies. Compared with difference-blind “non-establishment” they imply two important advantages: they tend to tackle the actual political and cultural hegemony of existing religious majorities more effectively and they tend to contribute more to actual religious pluralism in civil and political society. Difference-blind non-establishment either neglects inequalities and asymmetries of power in the world of religions completely, or, in the case of American liberal pluralism, it does not provide minority religions with relevant resources and political opportunities to correct them (they are not ‘brought onto the political stage’ effectively). “Constitutional pluralism” and “non-constitutional pluralism” do not only recognize the plurality of organized religions administratively and politically, as all institutional options inevitably have to, they add formal and legal recognition. They give them more clout by integrating them into the decision-making structure in specific fields and on specific issues. “Non-constitutional pluralism” is preferable to “constitutional pluralism”, in my view, because it expresses the principles of "priority for democracy" and public morality more clearly (see Bader 1999).
Substantive Equality
Arguments in favor of religious pluralism based on justice as fairness, not on perfectionist notions of the good life refer to equality, but equality is a very general, contested, and indeterminate moral principle.41 As we have seen, libertarians and radical individualistic liberals give absolute priority to liberty and accept only equality before and in the law. For them, the only institutional setting compatible with equality is “complete dis-establishment” because all other options are said to be inherently unfair either to other churches, other denominations, other religions, or to non-believers. Appealing to ‘equality and justice’ (48) as central moral principles, Jim Herrick, from a secular humanist view, thinks that only complete dis-establishment can ‘remove the injustice of Church privilege in relation to other denominations and other religions’ (PSI 47). Instead of extending legal privileges to other churches and religions it is better to remove them altogether. In his strictly separationist view, this also includes that the state should abstain completely from supporting religions in general, from subsidizing church schools (PSI 50) in particular.42 In a sense, this consequent position would, indeed, maximize strict or formal equality before and in the law, because there would be no legal or any other privileges at all and minority religions would have no opportunity to claim legal, fiscal or other privileges in complaints about unfair or unequal treatment.
All positions who do not completely sacrifice notions of social equality (of opportunities, procedures, of resources, of rewards, of status, of capabilities or whatever) have to think about measures how to tackle serious, deep-seated inequalities among religions. For them complete dis-establishment ‘is not required by the principle of religious equality’ (Parekh, PSI 20). They recognize that state policies in modern welfare states affect the diversity of religious believers and non-believers in direct and indirect ways, and that these policies cannot be completely neutral, neither in the justificatory sense (“secular purpose”) nor with regard to their consequences ("direct or indirect effect”, Bader 1999). This is obvious in many fields other than religion, like health (abortion, euthanasia etc.), education (curricula, pedagogy, financing, prayer in public schools).43
Here, I want to highlight only two general points. First, no general answers can be expected, because different situations in societal fields as well as differences between historical and institutional setting require differentiated policies, as theorists of contextualized morality have convincingly shown. Second, as shown above, policies can aim at facilitation or impediment of religions or they can take an indifferent stance. They can try to persuade, reward or punish, they can make use of a variety of means (laws, orders, money, other material resources, skills, information etc.). Whatever mix is chosen, all policies to redress serious inequalities have to be evaluated not only for their effectivity and democratic legitimacy, they have also to be scrutinized for unnecessary inroads against equality before the law. They all have to confront the nasty problems known from the affirmative action debates:44 Which religious minorities? The categorization of target groups is inevitable for institutionalization (for “procedural” participation in political deliberation, agenda-determination, development of alternatives for decision-making, decision-making, implementation and control) as well as for (re)distribution of specific benefits or burdens). How serious have inequalities to be to make political action necessary and potentially effective?45 Does the fact that these inequalities are deeply historically rooted, legitimize their continuation or, conversely, require additional attempts to guarantee more equal chances in the future?46 This difficult art of practical judgement should be guided by second order principles and the principles of "relational neutrality" and "fairness as evenhandedness" can do a better job than liberal models of neutrality and impartiality or radical differentialist partizanship. All options to institutionalize religious pluralism give religious minorities more voice and muscle than “complete separation” and “private pluralism”. By this, they stimulate public deliberation, the necessity to develop the arts of prudent balancing and of fair democratic decision making. In “weak establishment” such a balancing includes a price to be paid for the legal privileges of the established church and for the many subsidies for building churches, running special religious instruction, separate religious schools. It would be morally impermissible to neglect the claims of (organized) minority religions completely. In the ‘primus inter pares’ version of "constitutional pluralism", this price is more visible and fairness requires that the claims of newly developing (organized) religions should be treated in a sensitive way.
Dostları ilə paylaş: |