1.1.2 Evidentiality and Verbal Categories
In formulating evidentiality as E
n
E
ns
/E
s
, Jakobson (1957/1971) stated that he considered
evidentiality to be a high-level verbal category on par with tense, aspect, or mood. All of these
categories are composed of the following four pieces:
i.
E
n
- narrated events
15
ii.
E
s
- speech events
iii.
P
n
- participants of narrated events
iv.
P
s
- participants of speech events
These may be combined in a variety of ways, resulting in the ten categories shown in Table 4.
Table 4: Jakobson's Verbal Categories
P involved
P not involved
Designator
Connector
Designator
Connector
Qualifier
G
ENDER
S
TATUS
Quantifier
P
n
N
UMBER
P
n
P
e
V
OICE
E
n
A
SPECT
E
n
E
n
T
AXIS
Shifter
P
n
/P
s
P
ERSON
P
n
E
n
/P
s
M
OOD
E
n
/E
s
T
ENSE
E
n
E
ns
/E
s
E
VIDENTIALITY
The most important changes in Aronson’s (1991) new calculus of verbal categories
involved the redefinition of
STATUS
and the elimination of evidentiality as a verbal category.
Whereas Jakobson had defined
STATUS
as that “which characterizes [qualifies] the narrated event
without involving its participants and without reference to the speech event” (E
n
) (Jakobson
1957/1971, 134), Aronson defines
STATUS
as the “ subjective evaluation of the narrated event by
the speaker, i.e., E
n
/P
s
” (1991, 114 - emphasis added) and redefines
MOOD
using the formula
previously assigned to
STATUS
: E
n
. Evidentiality is only tentatively included in Aronson’s
calculus, as the quantification of a narrated event in relation to the participant in a speech event
(E
n
/P
s
). Aronson states that evidentiality should be regarded as “closely related to, or, better, a
subvariety of
STATUS
(E
n
/P
s
)” (1991, 116) as he knows of “no language that has a grammatical
category that has evidential as its invariant meaning” (1991, 130). Aronson’s verbal categories
are outlined in Table 5.
16
Table 5: Aronson's Verbal Categories
Characterizing the participants of a narrated
event
Characterizing the narrated event itself
With reference to the
narrated event
Without reference
to the narrated
event
With reference to
another narrated
event
Without reference to another
narrated event
Qualita-
tively
Quantita-
tively
Qualita-
tively
Quantita-
tively
Qualita-
tively
Quantita-
tively
Qualita-
tively
Quantitatively
E
s
E
n
/E
s
T
ENSE
P
s
P
n
P
s
P
ERSON
E
n
/P
s
S
TATUS
E
n
/P
s
E
VIDENTIAL
?
-
E
s
,
P
s
P
n
/E
n
V
ERSION
P
n
/E
n
O
BLIQUE
V
ALENCE
P
n
C
LASS
P
n
N
UMBER
E
n
/E
n
T
AXIS
E
n
M
OOD
E
n
A
SPECT
,
R
ESULTATIVITY
Aronson’s formulation of
STATUS
as involving P
s
reorients this category back toward the
speaker: the locus of evaluation and of knowledge. A number of recent theories relating
STATUS
or
MODALITY
and evidentiality relate these two ranges of meanings via the sorts of truth-value
judgments a speaker makes based on his or her knowledge. That is, when a speaker’s knowledge
is firsthand or shared with others, the speaker is more likely to be able to make an objective
evaluation of the truth of an utterance, whereas when a speaker’s knowledge is non-firsthand or
not shared with others, the speaker is less likely to be able to make an objective evaluation of this
truth (see Nuyts 2001).
This reformulation reflects Aronson’s previous work in which he claimed that
evidentiality should be viewed as a subtype of
CONFIRMATIVITY
, a subvariety of
STATUS
. On the
basis of data from Bulgarian, he proposed that when
NON
-
CONFIRMATIVITY
is expressed,
evidential meaning is a possible interpretation (1967). This analysis was expanded by Friedman
(1977; 1978, etc.) to account for phenomena in Macedonian, and later, Turkish, Albanian, Lak,
Avar, Georgian, and other languages of Eurasia.
A consequence of this non-confirmative analysis of so-called evidential markers is that it
allows a unified account of the apparent polysemy of these morphemes in many languages.
17
Morphemes expressing evidential meaning (and in particular, non-firsthand information source)
frequently express other non-confirmative meanings, such as dubitativity, non-volitionality, and,
most notably,
ADMIRATIVITY
.
Throughout much of Eurasia, evidential morphemes express a set of meanings termed
ADMIRATIVITY
(sometimes called “mirativity”), which is the linguistic expression of surprise at
newly discovered information. Admirativity was first identified as a phenomenon by Dozon
(1879) in his grammar of Albanian. Like evidentiality, its status as an independent category has
been a point of debate. Some scholars, such as DeLancey (1997; 2001) have claimed that it
merits the status of a category while others, such as Friedman (1988) and Lazard (1999) place it
in the category of
STATUS
or
MODALITY
.
Darden (1977) proposed that admirativity (in Bulgarian) could be accounted for by the
same means as evidentiality. Given different contexts, a morpheme bearing non-confirmative
meaning could bear either evidential or admirative meaning. In contexts where it is clear that the
speaker has not witnessed an event, the use of
NON
-
CONFIRMATIVITY
may result in the marking
of non-firsthand information source. When the speaker has clearly just witnessed an event, the
use of a non-confirmative form results in admirative meanings of irony or surprise.
The connection between evidentiality and non-confirmativity, or, at least, the speaker’s
evaluation of the truth of an utterance, is implicit in a number of terms employed by other
authors. The term médiatif, employed in a number of French-language works, refers to the
mediation of knowledge, and relates to the notion of the use speaker’s knowledge to evaluate
statements (Guentcheva 1996; 2007; Lazard 1996; 2000). This term is frequently employed in
discussions of evidential meaning in the languages of Eurasia, many of which employ non-
confirmative forms to express non-firsthand information source, admirativity, doubt, and the
18
like. In Turkic studies, the term indirective has been popularized by Johanson (2000; 2003) to
refer to this same range of meanings. He differentiates indirectivity from standard definitions of
evidentiality as follows:
The source of knowledge--the way in which the event is acknowledged by the conscious
subject in question--is not criterial; it is unessential whether the reception is realized
through hearsay, logical conclusion or direct perception. The receiver P is not necessarily
the speaker, P
s
, but may also be a participant of the narrated event, P
n
. Consequently,
markers of indirectivity do not fit into narrow evidential schemes primarily distinguishing
between the speaker’s non-first-hand and first-hand information (Johanson 2000, 61).
Because markers of non-confirmativity in Turkic express both non-firsthand information source
and admirativity, this distinction between pure information source and indirectivity is important.
While the claim of this work is that non-confirmativity is the most elegant way of accounting for
the morphemes that can express evidential meaning, the term indirective is a succinct way of
discussing the various consequences of the expression of non-confirmativity.
A number of recent typological works make the implicit claim that evidentiality is an
independent category. Among the broadest are those of Aikhenvald (2003; 2004). In these
works, she claims that information source may be broken down into six types (Aikhenvald 2004,
64):
Yüklə Dostları ilə paylaş: |