36
Necessity is a common law doctrine that provides a justification for otherwise illegal
government actions during an emergency.
133
It therefore bridges the gap between
what the law allows the government to do and the government's actual response to
an emergency: 'It has no relevance where emergency state['s]
action is taken
pursuant to specific statutory or constitutional [authorisation]'.
134
According to Schmitt, a state of exception is similar to a state of emergency
(necessity) but based in the sovereign's ability to transcend the rule of law in the
name of the public good. Schmitt argues that no legal factor such as a political
system or constitution can govern an extreme case of emergency or state of
exception.
135
According to Schmitt, legal factors cannot be applied to chaos, they
require a 'homogeneous medium'.
136
In an emergency, the application of the laws
through the usual administrative and judicial
channels leads to chaotic
consequences.
137
In the light of Schmitt's assertion, the sovereign in the case of Pakistan would be
the person or institution that invokes necessity, and therefore the state of exception
is the same, in practice, as a circumstance in which a state of necessity
determination is justified.
According to Schmitt, the issue is whether it is possible to establish legal conditions
for declaring a state of emergency along with constraints.
138
If the decision of
declaring an emergency is not subject to any
legal constraint it becomes
discretionary.
139
Therefore if the judges in Pakistan will always endorse the actions
of the politicians or the military, it in effect creates discretionary power in the
Pakistani judiciary, in the absence of the factors such as separation of powers
discussed further in Chapter 4.
133
Manby v. Scott, I Lev. 4 (1672), 'the law for necessity dispenses with things which otherwise are
not lawful to be done. . . ' in Mark M. Stavsky, 'The Doctrine of State Necessity in Pakistan' (1983)
16(2) Cornell International Law Journal 341.
134
Mark M. Stavsky, 'The Doctrine of State Necessity in Pakistan' (1983) 16(2) Cornell International
Law Journal 341.
135
Carl Schmitt,
Political Theology. Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty (G Schwab tr,
University of Chicago Press 2005) 11.
136
ibid 13.
137
ibid.
138
Lars Vinx, 'Carl Schmitt' (2014) The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy
accessed 24 October 2018.
139
Carl Schmitt, Political Theology. Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty (G Schwab tr,
University of Chicago Press 2005) 13.
37
Schmitt believes it to be impossible to anticipate the nature of future emergencies
and predict a solution. In his view it is not important to have a law in place that
determines who can take a decision in the state of exception:
140
'There can be a
'sovereign authority, even where such an authority is not recognized by
constitutional law'.
141
The quotation above seems to suggest a highly realist or cynical analysis in that it
depends who has the greatest power (possibly the military). All that matters is
whether there exists a person or institution (i.e. a sovereign) with the ability to take
a decision on the exception. The sovereign's act of
suspending the law does not
require legal recognition since 'the law's applicability itself depends on a situation
of normality secured by the sovereign'.
142
This situation, when seen through the
lens of the constitutional history of Pakistan, leaves the country in an untenable
position. In theory the armed forces of Pakistan are subordinate to the government,
but history has proved otherwise, for example, in the
case of the three military
regimes described in Chapter 4.
Schmitt believes that the act of emergency must be supported by a sufficiently large
and powerful constituency, otherwise such acts could hardly possess the factual
capability to suspend the law and to act successfully against the perceived
emergency.
143
Most of the time, dictators in Pakistan have initially ratified their act
of dissolution through the judiciary in the name of necessity,
144
then formed a
government with a sufficiently large and powerful constituency,
145
albeit one which
is un-representative of the country as a whole and in particular, certain provinces
that have only a minority of the population.
The Latin maxim
necessitas legem non habet (i.e. 'necessity has no law') used in the
cases mentioned in Chapter 4 was interpreted by Giorgio Agamben in setting out
his theory of state of exception
in two different ways, i.e. 'necessity does not
recognize any law' and 'necessity creates its own law' (
nécessité fait loi).
146
He argues
140
ibid 5.
141
Carl Schmitt,
Political Theology. Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty (G Schwab tr,
University of Chicago Press 2005) 12.
142
ibid.
143
ibid 5.
144
For example in the
Nusrat Bhutto case [1977] PLD [1977] SC 657 and
Syed Zafar Ali Shah case
[2000] PLD [2000] SC 869,
145
For example, Zia's PML (now PMLN) and Musharraf's PMLQ.
146
Giorgio Agamben, 'Chapter 1: The State of Exception as a Paradigm of Government' in
State of
Dostları ilə paylaş: